University of Kansas, Fall 2003
Philosophy 672: History of Ethics
Ben Egglestoneggleston@ku.edu

Assignment—Hume

Your assignment is either to take the test on Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature or to write a paper on that book. Note that, by the end of the semester, you must have taken tests on two of the four books in the course, and written papers on the other two.

You are welcome, though, to complete both of these assignments: to take the test and to write the paper. Then I’ll grade both of them and count whichever grade will help your overall grade more. This would be a good thing to do if you are nervous about either assignment and want a risk-free way of doing it and seeing what grade you would get. Here are the two options for Hume’s Treatise.

I. Test

The test will be given in class on Wednesday, October 15, and will consist of 110 or 120 points’ worth of the following questions. You will be asked to select 100 points’ worth of questions and to answer them. (Please bring a blue book or some blank paper on which to write your answers.) I’ve numbered them in the following way so that questions 1–12 correspond to the twelve questions labeled “possible test questions” in my lecture notes.

  1. (20 points:) Why, according to Hume, is reason incapable of motivating? (In answering this question, identify the two kinds of reasoning Hume countenances and indicate what role, short of actual motivation, Hume allows that reasoning of these two kinds can play in deliberation that leads to action.)
  2. (10 points:) Hume is known for denying the irrationality of certain preferences that are often thought to be paradigms of irrationality. What are two of Hume’s three notorious claims about not-irrational preferences?
  3. (10 points:) What explanation does Hume give of the prevalence of the belief that reason is capable of opposing the passions?
  4. (20 points:) How does Hume’s claim that reason cannot determine how we act provide support for his claim that morality is not based on reason?
  5. (20 points:) What, according to Hume, makes something virtuous?
  6. (20 points:) Why, according to Hume, is justice an artificial virtue, not a natural one?
  7. (10 points:) What are the circumstances that, according to Hume, make justice useful?
  8. (10 points:) What point is Hume making in identifying five different rules or criteria that are often used in order to decide how property rights are to be distributed?
  9. (10 points:) What inconvenience does Hume say is remedied by the custom of allowing property to be transferred by consent?
  1. (20 points:) What are Hume’s two arguments for the claim that promising is not naturally intelligible, but is intelligible only as a matter of convention?
  2. (10 points:) What are two of the “contradictions” that “are easily accounted for, if the obligation of promises be merely a human invention for the convenience of society” (3.2.5.13)?
  3. (10 points:) What are two of Hume’s three “farther reflections concerning justice and injustice” (3.2.6)? What conclusion are all three of these “farther reflections” intended, by Hume, to prove?
  4. (10 points:) What feature of human nature does Hume say mainly creates the need for a government? How does a government remedy this weakness in human nature?
  5. (20 points:) What widespread belief about the source of allegiance to government does Hume aim to disprove?
  6. (10 points:) What reasoning does Hume say is the right explanation for the fact that the duty of allegiance ceases when government becomes tyrannical?
  7. (10 points:) How, according to Hume, are the criteria for whom to obey partly logical, and partly arbitrary?
  8. (20 points:) What, according to Hume, explains the fact that people are more tolerant of violations of the laws of nations than they are of violations of rules having to do with respecting property rights and keeping promises?
  9. (10 points:) What is Hume’s explanation for the fact that chastity and modesty are valued in regard to women more than in regard to men?
  10. (20 points:) How, according to Hume, does sympathy enable certain character traits to be virtues and vices?
  11. (20 points:) One of Hume’s claims is that sympathy enables certain character traits to be virtues and vices. How does Hume’s invocation of the idea of a “steady and general poin[t] of view” enable him to reply to two objections that might be made to this claim?
  12. (10 points:) How, according to Hume, does his account of morality render not just virtue, but also the sense of virtue, worthy of approval?
     

II. Paper

The paper option is to write a paper of not more than 6 pages (double-spaced, 12-point type) on either (1) one of the following topics or (2) some other topic that you would like to propose to me (in which case, just let me know, and we can discuss it). Your paper will be due in class on Friday, October 17.

  1. Question 13, above, plus: Is Hume’s minimalist conception of the faculty of reason defensible? What are the pros and cons of conceiving of the faculty of reason in this minimalist way? Do the pros outweigh the cons?
  2. Question 14, above, plus: What reasoning for these claims can be found, explicitly or implicitly, in Hume’s text? Does this reasoning vindicate these claims? Why or why not?
  3. Question 18, above (to be answered in a more comprehensive, detailed, and text-grounded way, of course)
  4. Question 1, above, plus: Is Hume’s account correct? Or is promising naturally intelligible even according to Hume’s own criteria for whether something is naturally intelligible or not?
  5. Question 4, above, plus: Is Hume’s account of the creation of government coherent? That is, if humans are flawed enough to need government, how are they not so flawed that they are incapable of instituting government?
  6. Questions 10 and 11, above (to be answered in a more comprehensive, detailed, and text-grounded way, of course, and in a unified way)

In writing your paper you are welcome to use resources beyond those used in class, but you do not need to do so. For additional suggestions about writing philosophy papers generally, see my “Guidelines for Writing a Philosophy Paper.”