University of Kansas, Fall 2003
Philosophy 160: Introduction to Ethics
Ben Eggleston—eggleston@ku.edu
Class notes: introduction
The following notes correspond
roughly to what we cover, including at least a portion of what I put on the
board or the screen, in class. In places they may be more or less comprehensive than what we
actually cover in class, and should not be taken as a substitute for your own
observations and records of what goes on in class.
The following outline is designed to
be, and is in some Web browsers, collapsible: by clicking on the heading for a
section, you can collapse that section or, if it’s already collapsed, make it
expanded again. If you want to print some but not all of this outline, collapse
the parts you don’t want to print (so that just their top-level headings
remain), and then click here to print this frame.
-
introduction to the subject
matter of the course
- the three areas of ethics, or moral philosophy
- an example
- To understand the three areas of ethics, it helps to have a specific example in mind.
So think, for a moment, about the act of intentionally spreading a
computer virus. We can probably all agree that this is a bad thing for
someone to do.
- We can use this example to talk about the three areas of ethics.
- applied ethics
- This is the
branch of ethics devoted to the study of specific ethical issues.
- Regarding our example of spreading a computer virus, an applied
ethicist might focus on the ethical dimensions of computer viruses and
other kinds of computer-related behavior, such as hacking and spamming.
- An applied ethicist with a different specialty might ask whether
cloning is all right or whether we ought to treat animals better than we
do.
- Sometimes applied ethics is associated with the idea of “case
studies.”
- normative ethics
- This is the branch of ethics devoted (mostly) to the
development of moral theories: theories that specify, in brief and general
terms, what actions, policies, institutions, etc., are morally acceptable.
In regard to our example of spreading a computer virus, a normative ethicist would try to come up with a moral theory that
deals with this as just one of many different moral problems.
- For example, one normative ethicist might defend a theory whose
central principle is that the way to act rightly is to do whatever will
cause the most happiness. Such a theory would say that what’s wrong with
intentionally spreading a computer virus is that is decreases overall
happiness in the world by creating frustration for many people and
enjoyment for just a few. And this theory would tell us to judge other,
wholly unrelated, issues, such as cloning and animal rights, in the same
way: by looking at the consequences, in terms of future happiness, of
various policies and courses of action.
- Another normative ethicist might defend a theory whose central
principle is the golden rule. Such a theory would say that intentionally
spreading a computer virus is wrong because it involves treating other
people in a way that one would not like to be treated oneself: as someone
to be inconvenienced just for fun. And his theory would tell us to judge
other issues in the same way: in terms of the golden rule.
- meta-ethics
- This is the branch of ethics devoted to explaining what we are doing
when we make moral judgments or engage in moral debates. Meta-ethicists
try to give accounts of such things as the meaning of moral terms and
the grounds of moral judgments.
- Consider, then, the moral judgment, “Intentionally spreading a
computer virus is wrong.” In some respects, this judgment has the same
structure as an ordinary descriptive statement such as “This book is
blue”: it specifies a subject, and then uses the verb ‘is’ to ascribe a
property to that subject. This kind of consideration, along with other
kinds of considerations, leads some people to think that moral judgments
are basically like ordinary descriptive judgments. In other respects,
the moral judgment that intentionally spreading a computer virus is
wrong is like the imperative “Don’t spread computer viruses.” At least,
it functions sort of like that in conversation. This is the sort of
thing that belongs to meta-ethics: whether moral judgments are like
descriptive statements, such as “This book is blue,” or are like
imperatives, such as “Don’t spread computer viruses.”
- Whatever a meta-ethicist ends up saying about the statement
“Intentionally spreading a computer virus is wrong,” she would probably
also say about moral statements on other topics, such as “Cloning is not
immoral” or “We ought to treat animals better than we do.”
- areas of philosophy
- (You will not be held responsible for knowing this material—it’s
just to help you get oriented.)
- moral philosophy, or ethics: the study of right and wrong, or of
how we ought to live, or of what people’s duties and obligations are
- metaphysics: the study of
things such as what exists, what it is for one event to cause another, etc.
- epistemology: the study
of knowledge, when a belief may be regarded as knowledge and not
just conjecture or opinion, etc.
- philosophy of language:
the study of what makes words have meanings, how words refer to
things in the world (if they do), etc.
- philosophy of mind: the
study of what mental states are, how they differ, how they represent
the world (if they do), etc.
- philosophy of science:
the study of what makes something a science, how scientific theories are
confirmed, what makes something alive, etc.
- philosophy of religion:
the study of God, whether God exists, faith versus reason, etc.
- logic: the study of
correct reasoning
- others (aesthetics, political philosophy, etc.)
- introduction to the mechanics of the course
- review of syllabus
- a strategy for reading effectively before class
- read actively
- look for the author’s purpose
- ask yourself, “Why did the author write this chapter? How is he or she
trying to affect my mind?”
- take notes
- major divisions of the chapter
- important sentences
- places where (what seem to be) important concepts are introduced and
clarified
- places where things are said that you want to ask about
- what the lectures will be like
- rules
- cell phones off, no newspaper-reading, no conspicuous sleeping
- sit at the back if you come late or will be leaving early
- o.k. with me: eating or drinking quietly, dozing off
- general principle: if it’s distracting to me or other students, it’s a
problem; if not, it’s not a problem
- purposes and contents
- to complement other parts of the course, not to disseminate the bulk
of the
information
- to shed light on the hardest parts of the reading, not to recapitulate
it evenly
- to talk about things that aren’t in the reading, such as writing
- how I prepare to lecture, and then lecture
- prepare my lecture notes
- put them on the course web site
- print them out
- come to class
- lecture from the notes I’ve printed out
- sometimes make minor corrections
- some consequences
- Sometimes the notes from which I’ll be lecturing on a given day won’t
be ready (i.e., on the web site) until right before class.
- The notes from which I’ll be lecturing on a given day will be
available as of class time and afterwards.
- what’s on the web site versus what I say
- As I indicated, I lecture from the same notes that I put on the web
site. So just about everything I say in class will be associated with some
part of those notes.
- Often, though, what I say in class on a particular topic will be more
detailed than my notes are. In some cases, my notes may just contain a
word or phrase that will refer to a topic that I’ll spend several minutes
talking about. So the notes you take in class will end up being more
detailed, in certain places, than the notes on the web.
- It will frequently happen that I skip certain topics that are in my
notes. This is because in the past, I’ve said things in lectures that I
now think do not need to be said in lectures, but that my still be useful
for you to read.
- To help you match up the things I say in class to the parts of my
notes, I’ll try to say, in class, what part of my notes I’m currently
talking about.
- a strategy for managing your notes and consolidating your knowledge
- type or re-write your notes after class, filling in gaps while the
material is still fresh
- use your notes to elaborate on my notes
- one way of doing this: copy my notes to a word-processing file
(highlighting outline, not collapsing it), and copy and paste your notes
into the appropriate places
- another way: print out my notes (printing notes, not printing contents
column) and use labels (like endnotes) to refer to your notes
- re-read the assigned chapter, revising the notes you took earlier
- integrate those revised notes with your typed or re-written notes from
class (the ones you used to elaborate on my notes)
- EMP, preface (pp. ix–x)
- There are some fields, such as physics, in which there is a large body of
material that competent theorists or practitioners all agree is right. Of
course, physicists have some disagreements among one another—there is still
stuff to be figured out that different physicists have conflicting opinions
about—just as historians do not all agree on exactly what happened in certain
times and places in the past, and just as economists do not all agree on what
the best account of economic activity is. But in all of these fields, there is
a lot of fairly uncontroversial material.
- Philosophy is not like this; in philosophy there is very little that is
uncontroversial. So in this course we will be exploring many conflicting
views. None of them will be presented as the “truth”; rather, for the most
part, we’ll seek to understand the reasons for and against them. Ultimately,
you must try to decide for yourself what views have the strongest reasons in
support of them; my job will be to help you to identify and weigh those
reasons.
- EMP, chapter 1: “What Is Morality?”
- overviews of sections 1.1–1.4
- section 1.1: “The Problem of Definition”
- the idea of the minimum conception of morality: what just about
everyone agrees on, as far as morality is concerned, despite whatever
disagreements people may have about morality
- the point of considering some specific cases: to identify some
features of this “minimum conception of morality”
- section 1.2: “First Example: Baby Theresa”
- transplantation or not?
- for transplantation: benefits (to other babies)
- against transplantation: it’s “using” the baby. (But does it matter if
she is “used,” if her autonomy is not violated?)
- against transplantation: wrongness of killing. (But is killing always
wrong? And might it be claimed that the baby is already dead?)
- section 1.3: “Second Example: Jodie and Mary”
- surgery or not?
- for surgery: save as many as possible
- against surgery: sanctity of human life
- section 1.4: “Third Example: Tracy Latimer”
- killing justified or not?
- in defense: quality of life
- against: wrongness of discriminating against the handicapped. (But is
it really discrimination, or a reasonable distinction?)
- against: slippery slope (unverifiable predictions?)
- chapter goal, problem, and solution
- goal: to say what morality is
- problem: little agreement on what morality is
- solution: look at opposing positions on several controversies, and see
what they have in common
- the solution implemented
- examination of cases of Theresa, Jodie and Mary, and Tracy Latimer
- two things apparently held in common by all disputants (section 1.5)
- the dependence of moral judgments on good reasons
- This is the idea that moral judgments must be backed by good reasons (in
contrast to, say, judgments of taste). Mere “gut reactions” are not enough.
- Good reasons can be separated from bad ones by being careful about the
facts of a case, but this is not sufficient: people can agree on all the facts
but still reach different moral judgments.
- the requirement of impartiality
- This is the idea that moral thinking must count everyone’s interests
equally.
- This idea may be seen as a consequence of the dependence of moral
judgments on good reasons, since there seem to be no good reasons for not
counting everyone’s interests equally.
- section 1.6: “The Minimum Conception of Morality”
- These “lessons” from the three cases furnish the ingredients for a
basic characterization of morality: Morality is the effort to guide one’s
conduct by reason while giving equal weight to the interests of each
individual who will be affected by one’s conduct (p. 14).
- Note: this is not a definition, but Rachels’s view of what any
reasonable theory of morality must say. Most theories of morality do say
this; but there is a lot of disagreement in regard to what reasons are
good ones and in regard to what impartiality really amounts to.
- As a result, this minimum conception of morality ends up providing
very little guidance in making moral judgments. To see this, note that
just about everyone on both sides of the controversies discussed in this
chapter would agree with it (i.e., would agree that moral judgments must
be based on reason, and must be impartial). Rachels, of course, realizes
this; he isn’t touting the “minimum conception of morality” as the answer
to all our moral questions. Rather, his point (indeed the point of the
whole chapter) is to see whether there is some core of morality, common to
partisans on opposite sides of various issues. He finds that there is such
a core; but that since it is common to folks with such disparate views, it
can’t be expected to settle much.
- true or false?
- When Rachels gives his account of the “minimum conception of
morality,” he acknowledges that he‘s saying something pretty
controversial, like most things in philosophy.
- People who endorse Rachels’s account of the “minimum conception of
morality” will typically agree on what should be done in cases such as
those discussed in this chapter.
- People who endorse Rachels’s account of the “minimum conception of
morality” may well disagree on what it means to guide one’s conduct by
reason, or to give equal weight to everyone’s interests.
- Rachels could have used non-medical examples, indeed a whole different
set of examples, to come up with his “minimum conception of morality.”
- answers
- false
- false
- true
- true
- interlude: an introduction to arguments
- arguments
- definition
- An argument is a set of statements, one of which is understood to
be the conclusion, and the others of which are understood to be premises,
with the premises being offered as supporting, or providing reasons for, the
conclusion.
- an example of an argument
- (P1:) To discriminate against someone because of his or her handicap is
wrong.
- (P2:) What Robert Latimer did was to discriminate against someone—his
daughter—because of her handicap.
- (C:) What Robert Latimer did was wrong.
- Every argument has at least one premise, but there is no limit to how many
it can have. Every argument has exactly one conclusion.
- validity
- A valid argument is one whose conclusion cannot be false if its
premises are true. That is, it is one whose premises imply, or entail, its
conclusion. We often say that it is one whose conclusion “follows from” its
premises.
- an example of a valid argument
- See the example of an argument, above. That’s a valid argument.
- an example of an invalid argument
- (P1:) People don’t like what Robert Latimer did.
- (C:) What Robert Latimer did was wrong.
- A valid argument may have a true conclusion or a false one; likewise,
its premises may all or true, or some of them may be true, or none of them
may be true. The same goes for invalid arguments.
- soundness
- A sound argument is a valid one whose premises are true.
- It follows that the conclusion of any sound argument is true, too.
- valid or invalid? if valid, sound or unsound?
- first argument
- (P1:) Lawrence was founded in 1922.
- (P2:) If Lawrence was founded in 1922, then it is less than 100 years old.
- (C:) Lawrence is less than 100 years old.
- second argument
- (P1:) Either Kansas in the U.S. or France is.
- (P2:) France is not in the U.S.
- (C:) Kansas is in the U.S.
- third argument
- (P1:) Denver is in Colorado.
- (P2:) Las Vegas is in Nevada.
- (C:) Denver is in Colorado and Las Vegas is in Nevada and Los Angeles is
in California.
- answers
- valid but not sound
- valid—and sound, too
- invalid